Reports
The Limits of Counting:
Numerical Cognition Between Evolution and Culture
Sieghard Beller and Andrea Bender*
Number
words that, in principle, allow all kinds of objects to
be counted ad infinitum are one basic requirement for complex
numerical cognition. Accordingly, short or object-specific
counting sequences in a language are often regarded as earlier
steps in the evolution from premathematical conceptions
to greater abstraction. We present some instances from Melanesia
and Polynesia, whose short or object-specific sequences
originated from the same extensive and abstract sequence.
Furthermore, the object-specific sequences can be shown
to be cognitively advantageous for calculations without
notation because they use larger counting units, thereby
abbreviating higher numbers, enhancing the counting process,
and extending the limits of counting. These results expand
our knowledge both regarding numerical cognition and regarding
the evolution of numeration systems.
Department
of Psychology, University of Freiburg, D-79085 Freiburg,
Germany.
*
To whom correspondence should be addressed. E-mail: bender@psychologie.uni-freiburg.de
The
discovery of the largely restricted (1) or probably even
nonexistent (2) numeration system of the Pirahã in
the Amazonian Basin contributed to the discussion of how
numerical cognition depends on language. Numeration systems
are cognitive tools for numerical cognition (36),
and the experimental evidence gathered among the Pirahã
provided a sound basis for an analysis of how such tools
interact with the cognitive processing of numbers. Cognitive
tools, like tools in general, may be more or less efficient,
and respective differences in efficiency have been demonstrated
both for notational (7, 8) and for purely linguistic numeration
systems (912). It should be noted, however, that the
assessment of whether a feature is efficient always depends
on the nature of the task and on the context of usage and
that the efficiency of a specific numeration system does
not say anything about the cognitive abilities of its users.
Apart
from their efficiency, cognitive tools can also be ordered
according to their presumed evolution. Because tools are
typically developed in order to improve their efficiency,
it is reasonable to assume that numeration systems evolve
from being simpler to more sophisticated (6, 1315).
But can one also conclude that the simpler a numeration
system, the older it is? Although the authors of the recent
studies on the Amazonian cases were careful not to draw
this conclusion, the evolutionary status of the Pirahã
system has become a matter of lively debate, both inside
(2) and outside of academia. We propose that drawing conclusions
on the cognitive and evolutionary status of specific numeration
systems requires both diachronic and synchronic data. We
set out to highlight the cognitive efficiency of some allegedly
primitive systems in another part of the world and to show
how they may have evolved from abstract to more specific
as a result of cultural adaptation.
Among
the properties commonly taken as indices for the simplicity
of a numeration system are its extent and its degree of
abstractness. The two are largely independent of each other,
both on theoretical grounds as well as in practice, and
they differ in terms of the attention they have attracted:
Whereas the extent of numeration systems has been extensively
addressed recently (1, 2, 12), the degree of abstractness
has largely been neglected so far. We will illustrate these
properties with two instances for each but will focus on
the second feature.
One
region where systems with limited extent abound is Papua
New Guinea (16). Takia, a language in Madang Province, contains
five numeralskaik, uraru, utol, iwaiwo, and kafe-n
(also denoting "his/her thumb"). Higher numbers
may be composed by adding or multiplying numerals to the
word for 5, but this seems to have been done rarely and
for low numbers only (17). Adzera, a related language in
the Markham River valley in Morobe Province, contains an
even more restricted system. Its number words for 1 to 5
are composed of numerals for 1 and 2 only: bits, iru?, iru?
da bits (= 2 + 1), iru? da iru? (= 2 + 2), and iru? da iru?
da bits (= 2 + 2 + 1). Although because of its recursive
character this system is in principle infinite, the inevitable
difficulties in tallying the terms in higher-number words
render it cumbersome. In such cases, people nowadays prefer
to use loan words from Tok Pisin instead, a creole language
based on English and used as lingua franca in New Guinea
(18).
These
two numeration systems are admittedly not as simple as the
case of the Pirahã system, but their low bases and
the lack of higher powers of their base restrict both of
them. Although numerical cognition among the two Melanesian
groups has not been studied experimentally, it can be inferred
by analogy that, with such restricted systems, precise numerical
operations should be laborious, if not impossible, for larger
numbers (1, 12, 19).
The
second property that is readily taken as evidence for restricted
efficiency of a numeration system is its object specificity.
Menninger inferred that the more object-specific counting
sequences a language contains, the more antiquated the numeration
system is (14). One of the languages referred to as having
such object-specific counting sequences is Old High Fijian,
a language in the eastern part of Fiji: Whereas it denotes
100 as bola when canoes are counted, for coconuts koro is
used (20). Similar object-specific counting sequences can
be found in the related Polynesian languages. On Mangareva,
for instance, a volcanic island group in French Polynesia,
tools, sugar cane, pandanus, breadfruit, and octopus were
counted with different sequences (21). From an evolutionary
point of view, it appears reasonable to regard such specific
counting systems as predecessors of an abstract mathematical
comprehension. But surprisingly, these same systems often
also contained numerals for large powersas far as
109 in Mangarevanthus defining an extent not compatible
with the conception of "primitive" numerical tools.
Why
did we pick these particular instances? All four languages
belong to the same linguistic cluster, namely, to the Oceanic
subgroup of the Austronesian language family, and all inherited
a regular and abstract decimal numeration system with (at
least) two powers of base 10 from their common ancestor,
Proto-Oceanic (17, 22, 23). Both the relative limitation
of the two numeration systems in Papua New Guinea and the
specific counting sequences in Fiji and Polynesia therefore
constitute subsequent developments. Although the former
might count as a case of regression in evolutionist terminology,
the Polynesian cases are more complex and therefore require
an elaborate analysis.
Traditional
Mangarevan contained an abstract numeration system (Table
1) and three additional counting sequences for specific
objects (21). As can be seen from Table 2, each of these
sequences contained quantity terms different from the abstract
power numerals and appears to have proceeded in diverging
steps. However, this apparent divergence disappears when
the value of the counting unit to which these sequences
refer is extracted. For the first group of objects, the
smallest unit tauga equals 2, for the second it equals 4,
and for the third it equals 8 (for the polynomial composition
and the sequence patterns,
Specific
counting sequences were adopted in nearly every language in
Polynesia and even beyond, and they all operated with counting
units other than 1 (2527). However, despite being based
on the same construction principles, each of them was idiosyncratic
with regard to the value of counting units, the objects of
reference, and even to the numeration principles themselves.
This indicates that each culture adapted its inherited system
individually, in response to cultural needs. With only a few
exceptions, the specific sequences regularly accompanied a
general sequence that was purely decimal and abstract (28).
Because this general sequence is constructed according to
simple and coherent rules (Fig. 1A), it fulfillsunlike
the English or German sequences (4, 5, 911)all
of the requirements of a well-designed and efficient numeration
system. Why, then, the object-specific counting sequences?
One
of the remarkable facts about numeration systems in Polynesian
languages is their large extent. Clearly, Polynesians were
interested in high numbers and had a need to operate with
them (25). For instance, in precolonial times, Mangareva
was home to a highly stratified society and was a junction
for the long-distance exchange of goods. Accordingly, tributes
and large shares for trade were regularly due (2931).
However, without notation, dealing with large numbers is
difficult. In this context, specific counting sequences
served practical reasons.
Their
main effect was to abbreviate numbers by extracting from
the absolute amount the factor inherent in the counting
unit. This extraction has implications for critical factors
for mental arithmetic: It directly affects the problem size
effect in that it reduces calculation time (3), and it indirectly
affects base size (8). Although large bases are more efficient
for encoding large numbers and may, by virtue of compact
internal representations, facilitate mental operations,
they also require the memorization of larger addition and
multiplication tables. Small bases, on the other hand, are
cumbersome for the representation of large numbers but advantageous
when it comes to simple calculations. This holds particularly
for the binary system, as is well known since the work of
Leibniz.
In
Mangarevan, a preoccupation with 2 is apparent. Not only
do the three specific sequences differ with regard to the
value of their counting unit tauga by factor 2, but their
general decimal pattern is also modulated with elements
of a binary system. Because of its irregularities, the Mangarevan
system gave rise to disadvantages not faced by other Polynesian
languages with more-regular specific systems, but the disadvantages
were compensated by a range of facilitation effects.
One
of these effects was that counting specific objects was
enhanced by counting them in larger units (of pairs, quadruples,
or eights). In addition, extracting the respective factor
extended the limits of the counting sequence, but more importantly
it also abbreviated higher numbers and consequently combined
effects of large and small base sizes: Encoding produced
compact number representations (e.g., 48 ripe breadfruits
could be represented as 12 units = 1 paua +2 tauga) as in
a base 40 system; at the same time, calculating ensued with
the addition and multiplication tables of the decimal base,
supported by two binary steps.
To
sum up, the linguistic analysis reveals that the specific
counting systems in Mangareva did not precede an abstract
system but were rather derived from it, despite their nonabstract
nature (32). And the cognitive analysis suggests that this
was done deliberately and for rational purposes. This justifies
the conclusion that a feature of apparently little efficiency,
once taken as indicator for an earlier evolutionary step
in numerical cognition, can be used to overcome another
such feature.
Not
all cultures value numbers in the same way, even if they
are concerned with mathematical topics (33). In some cultures
in Papua New Guinea, for instance, large power numerals
were given up together with decimal systems and replaced
by quinary or body-counting sequences. In other cultures,
the reverse of this took place: Not satisfied with the restrictions
posed by their inherited numeration system, many Polynesian
cultures not only extended its limits of counting but also
designed efficient strategies to cope with the cognitive
difficulties of mental arithmetic. Both lines of development
started from the same regularly decimal and abstract numeration
system inherited from Proto-Oceanic and therefore speak
against a linear evolution of numerical cognition. Numeration
systems do not always evolve from simple to more complex
and from specific to abstract systems.
There
may be no other domain in the field of cognitive sciences
where it is so obvious that language (i.e., the verbal numeration
system) affects cognition (i.e., mental arithmetic). One
of the two core systems of number hinges on language (6,
34). If one's language does not contain numerals beyond
1 and 2, calculating larger amounts is difficult, if not
impossible. However, people are also very creative in adapting
their cognitive and linguistic tools to cultural needs,
and cases like those presented here add to our knowledge
of how they achieve this.
References and Notes
* 1. P. Gordon, Science 306, 496 (2004); published online
19 August 2004 (10.1126/science.1094492).[Abstract/Free
Full Text]
* 2. D. L. Everett, Curr. Anthropol. 46, 621 (2005). [CrossRef]
[ISI]
* 3. S. Dehaene, Cognition 44, 1 (1992). [CrossRef] [ISI]
[Medline]
* 4. S. Dehaene, The Number Sense: How the Mind Creates
Mathematics (Oxford Univ. Press, Oxford, 1997).
* 5. H. Wiese, Numbers, Language, and the Human Mind (Cambridge
Univ. Press, Cambridge, 2003).
* 6. H. Wiese, Lingua 117, 758 (2007). [CrossRef] [ISI]
* 7. R. S. Nickerson, Hum. Factors 30, 181 (1988). [ISI]
* 8. J. Zhang, D. A. Norman, Cognition 57, 271 (1995). [CrossRef]
[ISI] [Medline]
* 9. K. C. Fuson, Y. Kwon, in Language in Mathematical Education:
Research and Practice, K. Durkin, B. Shire, Eds. (Open Univ.
Press, Milton Keynes, PA, 1991), pp. 211226.
* 10. D. C. Geary, C. C. Bow-Thomas, F. Liu, R. S. Siegler,
Child Dev. 67, 2022 (1996). [CrossRef] [ISI] [Medline]
* 11. K. Miller, C. M. Smith, J. Zhu, H. Zhang, Psychol.
Sci. 6, 56 (1995). [CrossRef] [ISI]
* 12. P. Pica, C. Lemer, V. Izard, S. Dehaene, Science 306,
499 (2004).[Abstract/Free Full Text]
* 13. G. Ifrah, From One to Zero: A Universal History of
Numbers (Viking, New York, 1985).
* 14. K. Menninger, Number Words and Number Symbols (MIT
Press, Cambridge, MA, 1969).
* 15. F. Klix, Erwachendes Denken: Geistige Leistungen aus
evolutionspsychologischer Sicht (Spektrum Akademischer Verlag,
Heidelberg, Germany, 1993).
* 16. G. A. Lean, Counting Systems of Papua New Guinea (Department
of Mathematics and Computer Science, Papua New Guinea University
of Technology, Lae, 1992).
* 17. J. Lynch, M. Ross, T. Crowley, The Oceanic Languages
(Curzon, Richmond, 2002).
* 18. S. Holzknecht, Pac. Linguist. A-70, 77 (1986).
* 19. J. Wassmann, P. R. Dasen, J. Cross-Cult. Psychol.
25, 78 (1994).
* 20. C. M. Churchward, A New Fijian Grammar (Australasian
Medical, Sydney, Australia, 1941).
* 21. Les Missionaires catholiques de cet Archipel, membres
de la Congrégation des Sacrés-Coeurs de Picpus,
Essai de Grammaire de la Langue des Isles Gambier ou Mangaréva
(Imprimerie Zech et Fils, Braine-le-Comte, Belgium, 1908).
* 22. D. T. Tryon, Ed., Comparative Austronesian Dictionary:
An Introduction to Austronesian Studies (Mouton de Gruyter,
Berlin, 1995).
* 23. The common ancestor for a group of related languages,
if not documented, is reconstructed by way of a systematic
comparison of these languages. This method is inductive,
butbecause of the extensive database and the high
convergencethe reconstructed number words for Proto-Oceanic
can be regarded as firmly established. They are further
supported by a comparison with other Austronesian languages
ranging from Madagascar in the West to Easter Island in
the East (22). This comparison shows that the development
in parts of Melanesia must have taken place early on but
still was an exception in the larger Austronesian cluster.
* 24. If varu was the principal counting unit of the specific
sequences as indicated by cultural preferences, even the
unusual steps (i.e., paua and tataua) could be explained,
namely as short cuts to facilitate the representation of
the incomplete units. The specific sequence would then be
a modulo 40 system, in which units of 40 tauga were counted,
and the remainder (if any occurred at all) was decomposed
in 20 + 10 + n. This may not be the most efficient method
of decomposition, butgiven the generally decimal nature
of the systemit was surely the most preferable. The
next possible decomposition (20 + 10 + 5 + n) would have
arbitrarily restricted the single numerals to n isin {1,
2, 3, 4}.
* 25. A. Bender, S. Beller, J. Polynesian Soc. 115, 7 (2006).
[ISI]
* 26. A. Bender, S. Beller, Ocean. Linguist. 45, 380 (2006).
[CrossRef]
* 27. A. Bender, S. Beller, J. Cognit. Cult. 7, 213 (2007).
[CrossRef]
* 28. The switch from 10 to 20 in the general sequence in
Mangarevan is atypical in this regard. However, because
many of the traditional numeration systems were replaced
in colonial times before they were documented, information
on a regular system may simply have been lost.
* 29. P. Bellwood, The Polynesians: Prehistory of an Island
People (Thames and Hudson, London, 1987).
* 30. R. C. Green, M. Weisler, Asian Perspect. 41, 213 (2002).
[CrossRef]
* 31. P. V. Kirch, The Evolution of the Polynesian Chiefdoms
(Cambridge Univ. Press, Cambridge, 1984).
* 32. These conclusions can be further corroborated by an
analysis of the composition principles for the object-specific
counting sequences. It shows that these specific counting
sequences are derived from abstract counting sequences with
the aid of residuals of numeral classifiers [which, in several
languages, are obligatory in counting to specify and classify
the counted objects, such as words like "sheet"
in "two sheets of paper"; for more details see
(26)].
* 33. M. Ascher, Ethnomathematics: A Multicultural View
of Mathematical Ideas (Brooks/Cole, Pacific Grove, CA, 1991).
* 34. L. Feigenson, S. Dehaene, E. Spelke, Trends Cogn.
Sci. 8, 307 (2004). [CrossRef] [ISI] [Medline]
* 35. We are grateful to H. Spada for institutional support,
to A. Rothe for assistance with the material, and to S.
Mannion as well as two anonymous reviewers for discussion
and valuable comments on earlier versions of this paper.